class: center, middle, inverse, title-slide # Causality and Validity ## EDP 612 Week 7 ### Dr. Abhik Roy --- <script src="https://ajax.googleapis.com/ajax/libs/jquery/3.6.0/jquery.min.js"></script> <script type="text/x-mathjax-config"> MathJax.Hub.Register.StartupHook("TeX Jax Ready",function () { MathJax.Hub.Insert(MathJax.InputJax.TeX.Definitions.macros,{ cancel: ["Extension","cancel"], bcancel: ["Extension","cancel"], xcancel: ["Extension","cancel"], cancelto: ["Extension","cancel"] }); }); </script> <style> section { display: flex; display: -webkit-flex; } section p { margin: auto; } section { height: 600px; width: 60%; margin: auto; border-radius: 21px; background-color: #212121; } section p { text-align: center; font-size: 30px; background-color: #212121; border-radius: 21px; font-family: Roboto Condensed; font-style: bold; padding: 12px; color: #bff4ee; } #center { text-align: center; } .center p { margin: 0; position: absolute; top: 50%; left: 50%; -ms-transform: translate(-50%, -50%); transform: translate(-50%, -50%); } .center2 { margin: 0; position: absolute; top: 50%; left: 50%; -ms-transform: translate(-50%, -50%); transform: translate(-50%, -50%); } .tab { display: inline-block; margin-left: 40px; } </style> <style type="text/css"> .highlight-last-item > ul > li, .highlight-last-item > ol > li { opacity: 0.5; } .highlight-last-item > ul > li:last-of-type, .highlight-last-item > ol > li:last-of-type { opacity: 1; } </style>
--- class: highlight-last-item layout: true --- # Experiments and Causation --- # Cause -- + Variable that produces an effect or result -- + Most causes are **inus** - > A cause is an insufficient (**i**) > but non-redundant (**n**) > part of an unnecessary (**u**) but > sufficient condition (**s**) -- - A given event may have many different causes -- - Many factors are required for an effect to occur, but they can rarely be fully known and how they relate to one another --- # Effect -- + Difference between what did happen and what would have happened -- + This reasoning generally requires a counterfactual --- # Counterfactual -- + Knowledge of what would have happened in the absence of a suspected causal agent -- + Physically impossible -- + Impossible to simultaneously receive and not receive a treatment -- + Therefore, the central task of all cause-probing research is to approximate the physically impossible counterfactual --- # Causal Relationships -- A causal relationship requires three conditions -- 1. Cause preceded effect (temporal precedence) -- 2. Cause and effect covary -- 3. No other plausible alternative explanations can account for a causal relationship --- # Cause, Effect, and Causal Relationships -- + In experiments -- + Presumed causes are manipulated to observe their effect -- + Variability in cause related to variation in an effect -- + Elements of design and extra-study knowledge are used to account for and reduce the plausibility of alternative explanations --- # Causation, Correlation, and Confounds -- + Correlation does not prove causation -- + Correlations do not meet the first premise of causal logic (temporal precedence) -- + Such relationships are often due to a third variable (i.e., a confound) --- # Manipulable and Nonmanipulable Causes -- + Experiments involve causal agents that can be manipulated -- + Nonmanipulable causes (e.g., ethnicity, gender) cannot be causes in experiments because they cannot be deliberately varied --- # Causal Description and Causal Explanation -- + **Causal description**. identifying that a causal relationship exists between A and B -- + **Molar causation**. the overall relationship between a treatment package and its effects -- + **Causal explanation**. explaining how A causes B -- + **Molecular causation**. knowing which parts of a treatment are responsible for which parts of an effect --- # Causal Models <center> <img src="img/causality.png" alt="causality" style="width: 450px;"/> <center> --- # Causal Models <center> <img src="img/modmed.png" alt="moderator-mediator" style="width: 450px;"/> <center> --- # Modern Descriptions of Experiments --- # Randomized Experiment -- + Units are assigned to conditions randomly -- + Randomly assigned units are probabilistically equivalent based on expectancy (if certain conditions are met) -- + Under the appropriate conditions, randomized experiments provide unbiased estimates of an effect --- # Quasi-Experiment -- + Shares all features of randomized experiments except assignment -- + Assignment to conditions occurs by self-selection -- + Greater emphasis on enumerating and ruling out alternative explanations -- + ... through logic and reasoning, design, and measurement --- # Natural Experiment + Naturally-occurring contrast between a treatment and comparison condition -- + Typically concern nonmanipulable causes -- + Requires constructing a counterfactual rather than manipulating one --- # Nonexperimental Designs + Often called correlational or passive designs (i.e., cross-sectional) -- + Statistical controls often used in place of structural design elements -- + Generally do not support strong causal inferences --- # Experiments and the Generalization of Causal Connections --- # Most Experiments are Local but have General Aspirations -- + Most experiments are localized -- + Limited samples of **utos** > units (**u**) > treatments (**t**) > observations (**o**) > settings (**s**) -- + What Campbell labeled local molar causal validity --- # Construct Validity: Causal Generalization as Representation -- + *Premised on generalizing from particular sampled instances of units, treatments, observations, and settings to the abstract, higher order constructs that sampled instances represent* --- # External Validity: Causal Generalization as Extrapolation -- + *Inferring a causal relationship to unsampled units, treatments, observations, and settings from sampled instances* -- + Enhanced when probability sampling methods are used -- + Broad to narrow -- + Narrow to broad --- # Approaches to Making Causal Generalizations -- + Sampling -- + Probabilistic -- + Heterogeneous instances -- + Purposive -- + Grounded theory -- + Surface similarity -- + Ruling out irrelevancies -- + Making discrimination -- + Interpolation and extrapolation -- + Casual explanation --- # Statistical Conclusion Validity and Internal Validity --- # Validity -- + Approximate truthfulness of correctness of an inference -- + Not an all or none, either or, condition, rather a matter of degree -- + Efforts to increase one type of validity often reduce others --- # Statistical Conclusion Validity -- Validity of inferences about the covariation between treatment (cause) and outcome (effect) --- # Internal Validity -- *Validity of inferences about whether observed covariation between `\(A\)` (treatment/cause) and `\(B\)` (outcome/effect) reflects a causal relationship from `\(A\)` to `\(B\)` as those variables were manipulated or measured* --- # Construct Validity -- *Validity of inferences about the higher order constructs that represent sampling particulars* --- # External Validity -- *Validity of inferences about whether a cause-effect relationship holds over variations in units, treatments, observations, and settings* --- # Threats to Validity -- + Reasons why an inference may be partly or wholly incorrect -- + Design controls can be used to reduce many validity threats, but not in all instances -- + Threats to validity are generally context-dependent --- # Internal Validity -- + *Inferences about whether the observed covariation between `\(A\)` and `\(B\)` reflects a causal relationship from `\(A\)` to `\(B\)` in the form in which the variables were manipulated or measured* -- + In most cause-probing studies, internal validity is the primary focus --- # Threats to Internal Validity (1/2) -- + **Ambiguous temporal precedence**. Lack of clarity about which variable occurred first may yield confusion about which variable is the cause and which is the effect -- + **Selection**. Systematic differences over conditions in respondent characteristics that could also cause the observed effect -- + **History**. Events occurring concurrently with treatment that could cause the observed effect -- + **Maturation**. Naturally occurring changes over time that could be confused with a treatment effect -- + **Regression**. When units are selected for their extreme scores, they will often have less extreme scores on other variables, an occurrence that can be confused with a treatment effect --- # Threats to Internal Validity (2/2) -- + **Attrition**. Loss of respondents to treatment or measurement can produce counterfactual effects if that loss is systematically correlated with conditions -- + **Testing**. Exposure to a test can affect test scores on subsequent exposures to that test, an occurrence that can be confused with a treatment effect -- + **Instrumentation**. The nature of a measure may change over time or conditions in a way that could be confused with a treatment effect -- + **Additive and interactive threats**. The impact of a threat can be added to that of another threat or may depend on the level of another threat --- # Estimating Internal Validity in Experiments -- + By definition randomized experiments eliminate selection through random assignment to conditions -- + Most other threats are (should be) probabilistically distributed as well --- # Estimating Internal Validity in Experiments -- + Only two likely validity threats (typically) arise from experiments -- + Attrition -- + Testing --- # Estimating Internal Validity in Quasi-Experiments -- + Differences between groups tend to be more systematic than random -- + All threats should be made explicit and then ruled out one by one -- + Once identified, threats can be systematically examined --- # That’s it! Any questions?